Imagini ale paginilor
PDF
ePub

the question still remains whether such actions could ever be performed without the previous intervention of consciousness. It seems to me that we must still accept the old mystery of the union of body and soul as an ultimate fact which we cannot interpret, just because we have no other kindred facts with which to classify it. Looked at in the light of physical events in general, the actions of organisms seem to be self-sufficient. Yet the invariable appearance of consciousness with certain conditions in a living nervous organism is a fact which remains unexplained, and automatism obviously has no means of explaining it.

To this extent, then, I adopt the theory of automatism-so far as it affirms the à priori conceivability of complex nervous actions as purely physical processes. Accordingly, I hold that in the absence of the testimony of our own consciousness, and of organic conditions which clearly resemble those of human consciousness, inference respecting the existence of feeling in the physical world is, from a strictly scientific point of view, not only not necessary, but excedingly precarious.

B.

PHYSIOLOGY OF PLEASURE AND PAIN.

I HAVE not thought it worth while to enter into the question whether our maximum pains exceed our maximum pleasures. This point has not, so far as I am aware, been insisted on by the pessimists. It may be conceded that the worst conceivable combination of pains far surpasses the most delightful conceivable assemblage of pleasures. It would be hardly possible to name an intensity of enjoyment capable of neutralising a minute's bodily torture on the rack. It is this fact, probably, which has given rise to such sayings as that of Petrarch (Mille piacer non vagliono un tormento). Possibly, too, the concession of the English optimists of the last century, that our pains are in the main more intense than our pleasures, was deduced from this same circum

stance.

The consequences of this fact, supposing it to be ascertained, are not very important. That our organism is susceptible of a

[blocks in formation]

deeper and intenser amount of suffering than of enjoyment in a given time seems to be an alarming announcement, yet it is plain that it tells us little apart from the relative frequency of the causes of these maximum intensities of feeling. It by no means follows from this that our average pains surpass our average pleasures in intensity, and I think that this last proposition, though apparently admitted by certain optimists, is by no means true in the case of a healthy and fairly prosperous man or woman. Still, the point is worth considering in a complete survey of the question of pessimism. Let us see what light physiology throws on it.

In a work just published by Mr. Grant Allen, entitled 'Physiological Esthetics,' pleasure is referred to the normal action of a well-recruited nerve, pain to the destruction (disruption or exhaustion) of sentient tissue. In this common physiological theory of pleasure and pain the author ingeniously seeks an explanation of the fact that our maximum pains exceed our maximum pleasures. 'Massive pleasure can seldom or never attain the intensity of massive pain, because the organism can be brought down to almost any point of innutrition or exhaustion; but its efficient working cannot be raised very high above the average. Similarly, any special organ or plexus of nerves can undergo any amount of violent disruption or wasting away, giving rise to extremely acute pains; but organs are very seldom so highly nurtured and so long deprived of their appropriate stimulant as to give rise to very acute pleasure' (pp. 25, 26).

There seems to be considerable force in these observations. On a first view of the matter it looks as if the destruction of a tissue is unlimited, whereas the pleasurable normal action of a nerve is obviously limited by the store of energy at its disposal. Yet it seems to me that Mr. Allen presses the point too far. The painful wearing away of a single nerve is limited by the fact of total exhaustion, which, as I have remarked, is accompanied with insensibility. This effect may be produced instantaneously by a destructively violent stimulation, or after protracted stimulation. It is true that this stage of total exhaustion is rarely reached, and that painful stimulation of great force may go on for long intervals; yet it clearly presents a limit. If, instead of a small area of nerve, we take a large tract, the limit becomes still more distinct. The supposition of the whole nervous system being

racked with immeasurable torture for a single minute seems to be plainly opposed to the laws of life. Such a concurrence of violent stimulations would clearly destroy the organism. So, too, protracted intense pain in all sentient elements is biologically inconceivable. The facts of disease show plainly enough that such an amount of destructive action vastly reduces the capacity for suffering. Indeed, the very fact that pain is destructive, suggests on a deeper reflection that the sum of human torment, both for any particular interval, and absolutely, is a limited quantity.

Another point connected with the differences of pleasure and pain on which physiology might seem to throw light is the recollection of pleasure and pain. I have assumed in this work that where there is no special sensibility to pleasure or to pain, pleasures and pains are recalled with equal facility and in equal distinctness. Dr. Maudsley, in his recent volume The Physiology of Mind' (pp. 537, 538), speaks of a special obstacle to the recollection of pain, and thus appears to argue that pains are less easily recalled than pleasures. This obstacle lies in the fact that pains imply 'a disorganisation or disturbance of nerve element.' The reasoning is ingenious, and offers a tempting rejoinder to some of the arguments of Hartmann in favour of the predominance of pain. Does it, however, answer to the facts? Do we experience any greater difficulty in recalling a bodily pain, as that of sea-sickness, than a bodily pleasure, as that of a choice dish? The fact seems to be that the lower organic pains and pleasures are equally irrecoverable in idea, whereas the 'mental pains'-for example, those of defeated ambition are just as well remembered as mental pleasures. What determines the recoverability of a feeling is not its painful or pleasurable character, but its intellectual aspects and surroundings. Dr. Maudsley plainly recognises this in the passage from which I have just quoted. I would just add that in the case of a thoroughly healthy organism there appears to be, independently of volition, a special disposition to pleasure, and in this case, it is clear, pleasures will more readily survive in memory than pains.

[blocks in formation]

AHNSEN, Julius, his pessimism, 106-

ACTIVITY, an ingredient in ha310; B 108; on benefits of modern facili-

need renewed,

a factor in temperament, 421
Eschylus on the evanescence of life, 18
Esthetic view of universe, how far op-
timistic, 154

Alexandrine Philosophy, relation of, to
optimism and pessimism, 45, 46
Allen Grant on ratio of maximum
pleasure and pain, 469

Ambition social, how far an evil, 375,
376

Anaxagoras, his principle of intelligence
in the universe, 41

Anticipation, regulated by will a source
of pleasure, 296

Antiquity of man, doubtful, 395

Approbation, the love of, not illusory,
246, 247

Aquinas, Thomas, on predestination, 50
Aristotle, his view of the universe, 44;

his argument for difference of quality
in pleasure, 326

Art, Schopenhauer's doctrine of, 97, 98;
Hartmann's estimate of progress of,
254; an element in permanent in-
terests, 285

Asceticism, Schopenhauer's view of, 101,
102; relation of impulses of, to pessi-
mistic disposition, 424, 425
Association, bearing of,

on relative
amounts of pleasure and pain (Hart-
ley's view), 58, 259

Attention, relation of, to consciousness,
186-188; bearing of a control of, on
happiness, 290-298

Augustine, his view of evil, 48, 49
Automatism, theory of its bearing on
our inferences respecting the range of
conscious life, 202; Mr. Lewes's criti-
cism of, examined, 466-468

ties of travelling, 376

Bain, Alexander, his view of spontaneous
movement, 209; on the control of
feeling, 292; on the emotional and
active temperaments, 418

Bayle, Pierre, his theologic scepticism,
52, 53

Beneficence a source of pleasure to agent,

299

Bible, personal pessimism of, in the Old
Testament, 16, 17; optimistic theology
of, in Old Testament, 36, 37; in New
Testament, 46, 47

Biology, its relation to teleology, 200-
202; its theory of pleasure and pain,
271, 272

Birks, Professor, on the search for
Noumena, 198

Bradley, F. H., his objections to pleasure
as satisfying end, 310, 315
Brahmanism, its relation to optimism and
pessimism, 37

Brentano, Franz, his rejection of un-
conscious mind, 193

Brevity of life, bearing of, on life's value,
317-322

Brockes, Rathsherr, his naïve teleology,
65

Bruno, Giordano, his view of world, 51,

[blocks in formation]

CAR

Carlyle, Thomas, his relation to pessi-
mists, 14
Causation, law of, how conceived by
Schopenhauer, 85, 86; by Hartmann,
130, 131

Character, Schopenhauer's, analysed, 79-
82; Schopenhauer's theory of, 89, 90
Christian view of present life, 46, 47,
401, 402

Cicero, his complaint of contemporary

manners, 19; his presentation of judg-
ment of life in old age, 342
Civilisation, good and evil of, compared.
See Progress

Climate, effect of, on temperament, 434,

435

Comtism as a doctrine of social develop-
ment, 73
Condorcet, Marquis de, his view of human
progress, 71
Consciousness, how conceived by Scho-
penhauer, 89; genesis of, according to
Hartmann, 125-127; relation of, to
self-consciousness, 184-186; and to
attention, 186-189; range of, in phy-
sical world, 202-201: Mr. Lewes's
doctrine of, examined, 465, 468
Conservation of energy, bearing of law
on the theory of animal automatism,
202, 467

Conservative instinct, pains of, a deduction
from benefits of progress, 371
Contentment, meanings of, 306; in-
volved, together with discontent, in
pursuit of happiness, 306-312; grounds
of, recognised by hedonist, 312-315
Crime and immorality, influence of pro-
gress in diminishing, 136, 252, 369,
374

Critical temper, relation of, to pessimism,

423

Cynicism a half-hearted pessimism, 431;
affectation of, 444

Cynics, the, asceticism of, 43

DARWIN, Cetion as condition of pro-

ARWIN, Chas., his doctrine of na-

[blocks in formation]

Emotional susceptibility, individual dif-
ferences in, 332, 333; effects of pro-
gress on, 360, 362-365; variations of,
in relation to pleasure and pain, 403–
415

Emotions, laws of, 408-410

Empedocles, elements of pessimism and
optimism in, 40, 41

Endurance of pain, motives to, 423-425
Ennui, Schopenhauer's view cf, 94, 95;
its real nature, 234-236
Epicurus, his conception of good, 18
Europe, contemporary, pessimistic traits
of, 448. 450

Evil, existence of, different modes of
explaining away, 34, 35; how con-
ceived by Stoics, 44, 45; by Fathers,
47-49; by Schoolmen, 51; by Leibnitz,
53, 54; is not to be got rid of by
ontological or theological hypothesis,
156-158

Evolution, relation of, to teleology, 66,
67; its explanation of human progress,
382-397

Experience, the sole ground of reasoning
respecting worth of world, 156, 159;
variations of individual, 432, 433;
variations of social, 433-435

MATE, Greek doctrine of, 38, 39;

gress, 382, 383, 386, 387, 388, 391, Fearing of idea of, on pessimism,

393

Death, praise of, by Seneca, 20; by

Plotinus, 46; fear of, ridiculed by
Schopenhauer, 105

Deists, the, optimism of, 54, 55; their
conception of human progress, 70
Desire, Schopenhauer's doctrine of, 92,
93; real nature of, 213-217; voli-
tional control of, 294, 295, 338

152, 153

Fathers, the, their theodicy, 47-49
Fechner, G. T., on circumstances affect-
ing relative amounts of pleasure and
pain, 226, 229; on effect of contrast
between successive feelings, 231; on
physical conditions of pleasure and
pain, 265

« ÎnapoiContinuă »