Imagini ale paginilor
PDF
ePub

verses 11-21 Whom does the highest branch of the cedar represent? Who are denoted by the vine? What is meant by the plucking up and destruction of the cedar, and the withering of the vine? What analogy is there between transplanting a cedar, vine, and other plants, from one country to another, and the event which it is here employed to represent?

Let the scholar explain the parable of the supper, Luke xiv. 16– 24. What does the supper represent? Who is denoted by the man who made the supper? What does the invitation to the supper signify? Whom do those who refuse the invitation represent? Who, in distinction from them, do the persons next invited denote !

THE IMAGINARY FIGURE OF THE SPIRITUALISTS.

CHAPTER XI.

THE IMAGINARY FIGURE OF THE SPIRITUALISTS.

127

THE Comparison, metaphor, metonymy, synecdoche, hyperbole, hypocatastasis, apostrophe, personification, and allegory, are all the tropical forms there are, and all indeed that are possible. There is no conceivable mode besides them in which language can be used by a figure. When affirmations are made of agents, objects, qualities, acts, or conditions that are in accordance with their nature, and expressive of the facts as they appear to our senses and reason, then the language is absolutely literal. When direct and specific statements are made of the resemblances in nature, qualities, acts, conditions, or relations that subsist between dif ferent things, the language is always literal also; and the figure lies in the use of the things compared, for the purpose of illustration and ornament. When qualities or acts that are truly proper to agents or

objects are ascribed to them in degrees that exceed the reality, it is by the hyperbole. When natures, properties, conditions, acts, relations, are ascribed to agents and things that do not really belong to them, but only resemble what is proper to them, it is by the transfer to them by the metaphor of terms that are the proper names of differing things. When acts or conditions are ascribed to agents that are proper to them, or within the sphere of their nature, though not actually to take place, but that are, for the purpose of illustration and emphasis, substituted for others to which they bear a resemblance, that are to take place, it is by the hypocatastasis. When persons or things are called by names that are not proper to them, but are the names of things that have an intimate relation to them, it is by metonymy. When a part of a thing is called by the name of the whole, or the whole is called by the name of a part, it is by the synecdoche. When persons or things are directly addressed, in discourses that treat mainly of other subjects, and acts, properties, or conditions ascribed to them that are proper to their nature, it is by the apostrophe. When unintelligent objects are addressed as though they had the faculties and organs of intelligences, and acts or affections ascribed to them that are proper to persons, it is by the prosopopoeia, or per

sonification. And when agents, objects, acts, conditions, and effects of one class or sphere are used for the purpose of exemplification, to represent analogous agents, objects, acts, conditions, or effects of another class and sphere, it is by the allegory or parable. And these are the only possible forms in which language, acts, or things can be used by a figure. And in all these forms which involve propositions, the figure lies wholly in the affirmative part of the propositions, not in the names of the agents or things of which the affirmations are made. Thus when things are compared, the things compared are those which are directly named, not a different set for which those names are used by a trope. The nominatives of the propositions affirming the resemblances are always used literally. In the metaphor, the hypocatastasis, and the hyperbole, the names of the agents or objects to which the figure is applied are always employed in their literal sense. In the apostrophe and personification, the persons or things addressed are always literally those that are named as the objects of address. In the metonymy and synecdoche, the object of the affirmation is always that which is denoted by the noun as it is used by the figure. If Assyria, for example, is used by metonymy for the inhabitants of Assyria, it is to the inhabitants, not to the country, that the affirma

tion made respecting Assyria relates; and if the hand is used by synecdoche for the person, it is to the person that the proposition respecting the hand relates. And in the allegory and parable there is always an express indication who or what it is that the figure is employed to exemplify and illustrate.

There are many writers, however, who assume, and frame interpretations of the most important portions of the sacred Scriptures, on the assumption that there is still another figure; and that has the extraordinary peculiarity, that the nominative, or subject of the affirmation, is used by a trope, as well as the affirmation itself. No formal definition, indeed, is given by them of this imagined figure; and no exposition of its laws; neither are any examples cited of it; nor any direct proofs given of its existence. It is tacitly assumed, however, by thousands of writers in the exposition of the histories and prophecies of the sacred word, and constructions placed on them that proceed on the supposition, that if there be any figure in the passages giving the sense they ascribe to them, it must be of such an anomalous kind. It is obvious, however, that no such figure can exist, inasmuch as if the name of that to which the affirmation in a proposition is applied, were not used in its literal sense, it would be impossible to know who or what it is to which the

« ÎnapoiContinuă »